In Defense of Merit in Science

In Defense of Merit in Science

Merit is a central pillar of liberal epistemology, humanism, and democracy. This perspective documents the ongoing attempts to undermine the core principles of liberal epistemology and to replace merit with non-scientific, politically motivated criteria.

Table des matières

In Defense of Merit in Science

[Cet article, publié initialement dans le Journal of Controversial Ideas et signé entre autres par Abbot, D.; Bikfalvi, A.; Bleske-Rechek, A.; Bodmer, W.; Boghossian, P.; Carvalho, C.; Ciccolini, J.; Coyne, J.; Gauss, J.; Gill, P.; Jitomirskaya, S.; Jussim, L.; Krylov, A.; Loury, G.; Maroja, L.; McWhorter, J.; Moosavi, S.; Schwerdtle, P.N.; Pearl, J.; Quintanilla-Tornel, M.; III, H.S.; Schreiner, P.; Schwerdtfeger, P.; Shechtman, D.; Shifman, M.; Tanzman, J.; Trout, B.; Warshel, A.; West, J. dont deux prix Nobel, prend la défense de la méritocratie.]

On lira le même article au format PDF avec un apparat critique développé ici-même.

Merit is a central pillar of liberal epistemology, humanism, and democracy. The scientific enterprise, built on merit, has proven effective in generating scientific and technological advances, reducing suffering, narrowing social gaps, and improving the quality of life globally. This perspective documents the ongoing attempts to undermine the core principles of liberal epistemology and to replace merit with non-scientific, politically motivated criteria. We explain the philosophical origins of this conflict, document the intrusion of ideology into our scientific institutions, discuss the perils of abandoning merit, and offer an alternative, human-centered approach to address existing social inequalities.

1. Introduction

We live in an incredible time of human history. As Barack Obama said: “If you had to choose one moment in history in which you could be born, and you didn’t know ahead of time who you were going to be—what nationality, what gender, what race, whether you’d be rich or poor, gay or straight, what faith you’d be born into … you would choose right now.” While the benefits of significant global progress and economic development have not been shared equally, the world as a whole has never been healthier, wealthier, better educated, and in many ways more tolerant and less violent, than it is today.1,2

How did we get here? Science provided solutions to such calamities as famine and plague, transforming them “from incomprehensible and uncontrollable forces of nature into manageable challenges.”1 By improving the world economy and increasing global wealth, scientific progress helped create a more peaceful and just world. Science eradicated smallpox, discovered penicillin, decoded the SARS-CoV-2 virus in a weekend, helped to halve the maternal and child mortality rate globally, revolutionized agriculture, contributed to extending life expectancy in every country, and has generally granted humanity the gifts of life, health, wealth, knowledge, and freedom. By increasing literacy and communication, science has promoted empathy and rational problem-solving, contributing to a global decline in violence of all forms.1,2

Of course, serious problems continue to challenge us; poverty, inequality, wars, and violence persist. Climate change, biodiversity loss, antimicrobial resistance, and pandemic disease threaten global gains made over the past century. However, science continues to be the best tool humanity possesses to address these complex, collective challenges. Indeed, science holds the key to solving these problems—it provides the basis for renewable energy technologies, mitigating anthropogenic impact on the global climate, feeding the world’s growing population, controlling pandemics, and eradicating debilitating diseases. Of course, science alone is not sufficient: science is but a tool that can be used for good and bad. It is our responsibility as a society to use it responsibly, ethically, and effectively.

Fulfilling this responsibility, however, is being hindered by a new, alarming clash between liberal epistemology and identity-based ideologies. Liberal epistemology prizes free and open inquiry, values vigorous discourse and debate, and determines the best scientific ideas by separating those that are true from those that are likely not. The statuses, identities, and demographics of scientists are irrelevant to this great sifting of valid versus invalid ideas.

In contrast, identity-based ideologies seek to replace these core liberal principles, essential for scientific and technological advances, with principles derived from postmodernism and Critical Social Justice (CSJ), which assert that modern science is “racist,” “patriarchal,” and “colonial,” and a tool of oppression rather than a tool to promote human flourishing and global common good.3,4,5,6,7,8

In this perspective, we explain the differences between the two epistemologies and argue that meritocracy9 (grounded in philosophical liberal epistemology), however imperfect, is the best and fairest way to conduct science. We endorse policies to mitigate existing inequalities of opportunities, but explain why CSJ-based policies are pernicious (CSJ differs from social justice as a concept6,7). Therefore, we offer a liberal, humanistic alternative that is compatible with maximizing scientific advances.


2. Merit-Based Science is Effective and Fair

Why science is an engine that propels societies to health, wealth, and prosperity—ultimately saving and improving lives worldwide—is well understood.1,2 The cornerstone of science is the notion that objective truth exists and can be understood through observation, experiment, and iterative hypothesis generation. Because objective truth exists, ultimate consensus among truth-seeking actors—scientists—is possible.

The scientific method has proven an effective tool for revealing objective truths about the natural world. These truths are not final and immutable, but provisional—open to challenge and refinement as knowledge expands. For example, quantum mechanics has shown that the laws governing the motion of billiard balls and planets are not sufficient to describe the motion of nuclei and electrons. Yet, the Schrödinger equation does not invalidate Newton’s Laws, which we continue to use to engineer cars, airplanes, and rockets. Rather, quantum mechanics expanded our understanding of reality by revealing that classical mechanics is limited to the macroscopic world. In much the same way, Einstein’s theory of relativity did not negate Newton’s law of universal gravitation—it extended it to include new phenomena such as black holes.

The scientific method is the core of liberal epistemology. In The Constitution of Knowledge,10 Rauch addresses the current epistemological crisis by reaffirming the central tenets of liberal epistemology (developed by Popper, Albert, Weber, and others). Namely, that provisional truth is attainable and that a truth claim can be made only if it is testable and withstands attempts to debunk it (the Fallibilist Rule). He also emphasizes that no one has personal authority over a truth claim, nor can one claim authority by virtue of a personally or tribally privileged perspective (the Empirical Rule). Similarly, truth claims cannot be less valid by virtue of the claimant’s membership in any particular group. Liberal epistemology implies that “positionality statements” (in which scientists disclose their demographic identity memberships and which are now being advocated throughout academia) have no value in evaluations of scientific claims,11 since the validity of a truth claim cannot be evaluated by knowing the claimants’ tribal or demographic affiliations.12 In liberal epistemology, the validity of truth claims can only be evaluated by evidence and the logic of inferential processes linking that evidence to further conclusions.

However, evaluating the quality of that evidence or the validity of the inferential processes is itself a social process, a point upon which some liberal10 and feminist13 philosophers agree. In both Rauch’s10 and Longino’s13 perspective, no one has final say; scientific truths are determined by an ongoing social process that includes discussion, debate, and criticism until a broad consensus is reached (and which can be challenged by new evidence and arguments). Although both perspectives permit all members to participate in the social process of truth-seeking, in neither perspective is truth determined by the group-based identities of the claimant.

Further, reality-based scientific communities must be open to conceding and correcting errors. The ability of science to self-correct—one reason that scientific truth claims are uniquely credible10,12—can be epistemically contrasted with conformity to religious and political dogmas, which are disturbingly closed to self-correction. Self-correction is facilitated by pluralism to maintain intellectual diversity and maximize the chances of uncovering provisional truths. Intellectual diversity ensures vigorous skeptical vetting of scientific claims by a critical mass of doubters who ultimately accept being bound by objective truths once they have been rigorously determined by extensive evidence.

These core principles, which have served us well for centuries, are under attack by ideologies originating in postmodernism and Critical Theory,6,10,14 versions of which reject objective reality in favor of “multiple narratives” promulgated by different identity groups and “alternative ways of knowing.” They engender “radical skepticism about whether objective knowledge or truth is obtainable” and “a commitment to cultural constructivism,” which asserts that knowledge and reality are products of their cultural context.3,4 When claims about lived experiences and subjectivism are proposed to constitute a better basis for understanding the world than empirical evidence and facts, the identity of participants in a discourse becomes more important than the substance of their arguments or the strength of the evidence, and objectively adjudicating claims becomes impossible.

These perspectives often view science as a tool of power, are hostile to the central liberal principle of free inquiry and open discussion, and are closed to calls to justify their claims on scientific grounds.

Such ideologies suffer from at least two serious philosophical problems. The first is that their rejection of objectivity undermines their credibility. If there is no objectivity, then their claims are not objectively true. If their claims cannot possibly be objectively true, there is no reason for anyone to believe them. Their claims warrant serious consideration only if they might actually be true—which requires at least the possibility of objectivity.

The second is that these philosophies3 conflict with a set of principles of modern science known as the Mertonian norms (see Figure 1).12 Merton, a founder of sociology of science, formulated these principles based on his analysis of factors that enabled the scientific revolution and explained that they are dictated by the goals of science. Indeed, following these principles has served us well, and, as we argue below, a departure from these ideas has a long history of harming science.15,16,17,18,19

Together, the Mertonian principles imply that merit must be the key metric to judge and evaluate scientific claims. The merit of an idea should be evaluated through scrutiny and organized skepticism, essential components of scientific discovery. The ultimate test of the merit of a claim is its ability to accurately predict the functioning of the universe as elucidated through replicable experiment and observation, not whether it feels right or comports with a particular worldview or group interest. Ideological orthodoxies deserve no place in science.


3. How to Apply Merit: Caveats, Pitfalls, and Good Practices

The primacy of merit-based scientific truth claims raises the following question: How can we apply merit consistently and effectively? Although it may be straightforward to rank chess players, ranking prospective students, job applicants, tenure candidates, and scientific proposals is more difficult. Judgment may be affected by personal preferences, blind spots, and biases. Yet there are established good practices that have been honed and refined over decades.

In assessing merit and scientific promise, quantitative metrics have benefits, despite their limitations.28 While merit cannot be quantified by simplistic formulas (e.g., number of publications times impact factor), using numerical data to quantify scientific output is a useful component of the evaluation because it provides a quantitative measure of productivity. Good practices currently use a combination of quantitative metrics and qualitative assessment, e.g., letters from reviewers assessing how influential, original, and innovative the work is.

Although we view objective quantifiable metrics (such as publications) as one important dimension of merit, merit cannot be reduced to bean counting. Is one superb publication more valuable than four pretty good ones? This is a judgment call about which different people and institutions may honestly disagree. And what makes a published report “superb” will differ among fields and institutions. Although subjective judgments should play an important role in evaluations of merit, we recognize that they are also most vulnerable to biases.

How, then, can the potential for bias be mitigated so that even subjective judgments have a laser-like focus on merit? We suggest that two questions are central to the evaluation of scientific merit (see Figure 2): (1) How important is the finding? (2) How strongly does the evidence presented indicate that the main claims are true?

Differences of opinion may exist regarding both of these dimensions. However, the key is that focusing on the importance of the finding and the strength of evidence can limit bias. Astronomers may value the discovery of a new exoplanet more than material scientists value improvements in ceramic tensile strength, but this is normal science and can be threshed out among scientists. The identity or positionality of the authors is irrelevant.

Merit also includes mentoring students. Again, numerical data related to the professional development of a candidate’s mentees (papers published, conference presentations delivered, awards received, graduation rate, job placements, etc.) are helpful to build an overall assessment of merit. Academic promotion panels also consider teaching, professional and public service, and community engagement.

Many universities use quantitative indicators to compare individuals working in similar areas at similar career stages to detect deviations and create benchmarks of performance. It is recognized that quantitative metrics vary greatly among fields and depend on the nature of a position (e.g., teaching undergraduates versus graduate-level research) and this is justifiably taken into consideration when appraising academic performance.

Qualitative and subjective judgments are also important. There may be genuine differences of opinion about whether mentoring one student who goes on to be an academic research star is a greater or lesser accomplishment than mentoring five students, four of whom go into industry and one who becomes an academic at a small liberal arts college. But the value of just counting, however imperfect, should be obvious: all else equal, mentoring one star is better than mentoring no stars; mentoring four students who go on to professional careers in industry is more of an accomplishment than mentoring none. Again, though, the identity or positionality of the mentor is irrelevant to the evaluation of merit when using these sorts of quantitative metrics.


4. The Perils of Replacing Merit with Social Engineering and Ideological Control 4.1. Lessons from History

The universalism of science does not preclude culture and politics from being involved in funding priorities. Funders, whether government or private, expect to receive a return on their investment. Yet politicians should not dictate how science is done, and political agendas should not replace Mertonian norms. History demonstrates the dangers of replacing merit-based science with ideological control and social engineering.16,17,19 In the Soviet Union (USSR), the aberrations of Trofim Lysenko had catastrophic consequences for science and society.17 An agronomist and “people’s scientist” who came from the “superior” class of poor peasants, Lysenko rejected Mendelian genetics because of its supposed inconsistency with Marxist ideology. Dissent from Lysenko’s ideas was outlawed and his opponents were fired or prosecuted. Lysenko’s ideologically infused agricultural ideas were put into practice in the USSR and China, where, in both countries, they led to decreased crop yields and famine.17 Today, biology is again being subjugated to ideology—medical schools deny the biological basis of sex, biology courses avoid teaching the heritability of traits, and so on.29,30 More examples of ideological subversion of science, relevant to physics and chemistry, were discussed in a recent viewpoint.19

Such analysis19 is often dismissed with vague deflections such as “everything is political” and “everyone is biased.” There is an element of truth to these declarations, which can help raise awareness of the potential of scientists to have biases, including biases on politicized topics, and help minimize such biases. However, those making these arguments often use them to impose their own ideological agendas on what can be studied and what kind of answers are permissible.31 It is this sense of the politicization of science that we categorically oppose.
4.2. The Damage Inflicted by Today’s Politicization of Science

The lessons from history are clear: ideological control of the scientific enterprise leads to its decline. The ongoing ideological subversion of STEMM (science, technology, engineering, mathematics, and medicine) education is particularly worrying. Ideological changes in the U.S., Canada, and New Zealand are already under way32,33,34 and are quickly influencing other democracies.

The worst excesses of CSJ ideology are spreading to medicine, psychology, and global public health with worldwide implications.25,26,35,36,37 For example, in global public health, the ideology manifests in the Decolonize Global Health movement, which calls for dismantling global health, questions research-based knowledge, emphasizes intergroup and international antagonisms, and challenges universalism as an ideal for global health, humanitarian aid, and development assistance.37

CSJ-driven pedagogy can be pernicious, even when proposed innovations appear benign. For example, the proposed curriculum decolonization in pharmacology38 involves teaching about drugs developed from folk remedies and focusing on the contributions of non-Europeans. While such topics might be appropriate for a history of medicine course, centering the curriculum around them, as has been proposed, would be detrimental to training health professionals. The vast majority of today’s pharmacopeia is derived from the research and development efforts of the modern pharmaceutical industry; effective treatments derived from traditional medicine are rare, especially in the era of bio- and immunotherapies. For example, of the over 150 anti-cancer drugs available today, only three are of natural origin (trabectedin, taxanes, and vinca-alkaloids).39 Decolonizing pharmacology also contributes to the public’s infatuation with traditional medicine, while health agencies report numerous therapeutic accidents involving herbal products not validated following “colonial” standards.40 Such pedagogy also reinforces mistrust toward “white medicine,” feeding conspiracy theories against the pharmaceutical industry, as exemplified by campaigns against COVID vaccines, which, sadly, disproportionately impacted minority groups.41

Scientific research requires dedication, intensive technical training, and a commitment to rigor and truth-seeking. Weakening merit-based admissions, created to identify and cultivate the best and brightest, will have long-lasting consequences for the scientific workforce, discouraging or preventing many promising students from entering the field. Signs of this are already evident. The weakening of the workforce in the U.S. has contributed to that country’s recent fall from the position of world leader in science.15 If the movement in North America to replace merit with ideology in funding42,43,44,45 and faculty hiring46,47,48,49,50 progresses, further deterioration in the ability to foster excellence in research in the U.S. is all but inevitable. This does not bode well for the future of science and society globally.

Enforcing identity-based hiring is discriminatory,51,52,53 as it deprives some high-achieving individuals, including economically disadvantaged individuals who are not members of politically favored identity groups, of opportunities they have earned,54,55,56,57 thereby potentially damaging morale and engagement. In the U.S., this has resulted in the unfair treatment of Asian-American, Jewish, white, male, and foreign students.32,52,53,56,57,58,59

Ironically, replacing universalist principles with identity-based selection risks ultimately harming qualified underrepresented researchers by introducing doubt as to whether they merited their position or were hired for ideological reasons. Attempts to demonize, inflict reputational damage, or silence critics of social engineering practices by characterizing them as racists, white supremacists, or worse46,60,61,62,63 is particularly detrimental to the open intellectual environment in which scientific inquiry into difficult social problems thrives. For every incident in which a scientist is targeted, thousands get the message and self-censor.60,61,63

Besides directly impacting the scientific enterprise, the ideological capture of scientific institutions19,31,64 has broad consequences for society. Scientists and scientific institutions have a responsibility to enhance understanding and acceptance of the scientific consensus on matters of public importance. As seen with climate change and COVID-19, once a scientific topic becomes politicized, trust in science diminishes, laying the groundwork for science denial, conspiracy theories, and political opportunism.37 Research has consistently shown that public acceptance of a scientific consensus is driven not by scientific literacy (accepters are no more knowledgeable than deniers) but by political ideology and trust in scientific institutions.65 When scientific institutions issue political position statements and adopt identity-based policies, they alienate and lose the trust of large dissenting segments of the public.66 When prominent scientific journals promote these ideologies through editorials and perspective pieces, they magnify the alienation. Conflicting with the Mertonian principles of disinterestedness and universalism, these manifestos undermine the credibility of science as an objective, disinterested, and truth-seeking enterprise.

5. The Genesis of the Current Attacks on Merit-based Science

The ideological basis of the current attacks on science emanates from certain veins of postmodernism and the identity-based ideologies they have spawned: various CSJ theories, including Critical Race Theory (CRT), related theories of structural racism, and postcolonial theory.3,4,5,6,14

These ideologies are increasingly finding their way into politics, culture, and education and are negatively affecting science, medicine, technology, psychology, and global health.15,25,26,34,37 They are not imposed by totalitarian regimes, but spread by activists and abetted by university administrators and business leaders who fail to protect their institutions from these illiberal, regressive ideas.60,63,68 The genesis of these ideologies is often obscure to the public or even to their bearers—e.g., administrators trained in Diversity, Equity, and Inclusion (DEI)—who are unlikely to have read Gramsci, Derrida, Foucault, Bell, Crenshaw, and Delgado. But just as a Soviet apparatchik need not have read Das Kapital to have been an agent ensuring conformity to Marxist doctrine, one need not be fully versed in postmodern or CRT-inspired scholarship to be implementing the ideology. The problems emerge from doctrinaire implementation, not from deep knowledge of the scholarship.

Critical Theory and CSJ conflict with the liberal Enlightenment. According to Delgado and Stefancic,5 their characteristic elements include anti-rationalism; anti-enlightenment; rejection of equal treatment, philosophical liberalism, and neutrality in law; standpoint epistemology and subjectivism as the basis of knowledge; and intersectionality. Recently, ideas that emerged from Critical Theory have been aggressively disseminated to the public, notably in books by DiAngelo and Kendi,69,70 now promoted as essential reading in many schools and universities.

Critical Theories seek to fundamentally change the practice of science.10,14 Figure 3 contrasts CSJ epistemology with the ideas of the liberal Enlightenment.

CSJ is not an empirical theory, because its tenets are maintained despite their being either demonstrably false or unfalsifiable.3,6,7,10,14 The existence of objective reality, for example, which CSJ denies, is attested to by every successful engineering project, from bridges to satellites, from cell phones to electric cars, ever conducted. The fallibility of “lived experience” is attested to by a wealth of psychological research demonstrating errors and biases in self-reports.71 Yet, CSJ has found its way into STEMM, evoking parallels with the ideological corruption of science of past totalitarian regimes.19 As an illustration, The Lancet published a paper in 2020 titled “Adopting an Intersectionality Framework to Address Power and Equity in Medicine”72—a call to adopt CSJ ideology in medical education and practice. This is reminiscent of the ideological control of science16,17,19 and medicine18 in the USSR. In medicine, Marxist ideology manifested itself in “‘workerizing’ … [the] apparatus [of medical care]” (i.e., selecting future doctors from the working class, rather than the intelligentsia by means of class-based quotas) and prioritizing medical care for citizens based on class (the proletariat was to be given higher priority than the farm workers; the farm workers, higher priority than the intelligentsia; and so on).18

The CSJ view—that institutions of knowledge, art, and law perpetuate systemic racism and, therefore, must be dismantled, and that merit-based criteria in hiring, publishing, and funding must be replaced with CSJ criteria—has been aggressively advanced by many of our academic leadership—university administrators, executive bodies of professional societies, publishers, etc. A search for “racism” in the titles of papers published by the Science and Nature Publishing groups returns hundreds of hits such as “NIH Apologizes for ‘Structural Racism,’ Pledges Change,”73 “Dismantling Systemic Racism in Science,”74 and “Systemic Racism in Higher Education.” This reflects the axiomatic ideological perspective of CSJ that systemic racism is indelibly etched into every Western institution. The perspective is taken as an article of faith, which is why some have argued that CSJ is more a secular religion than an evidence-based science.75

Below we discuss publications making unsupported claims of systemic injustices and attacking merit. Such publications rarely, if ever, provide evidence that observed disproportionalities in the race or gender distribution of a scientific field are the result of present-day structural or systemic racism. Whereas historical events, such as apartheid, slavery, and Jim Crow, are beyond dispute, the extent to which systemic racism influences STEMM or academia today is a contested question.76 Its existence cannot be established by proclamation. In the absence of compelling evidence, these assertions are not scientific; they are dogma. In his book Discrimination and Disparities,76 Sowell takes to task the central axiom of CSJ—that disparate outcomes for various social groups emerge as a result of discrimination—and presents ample evidence illustrating its fallacy. Sowell’s arguments present compelling counterpoints to the standard set of arguments against meritocracy, such as those presented in The Tyranny of Merit77 and The Meritocracy Trap.78

Space considerations do not permit a full evaluation of the arguments, many of which boil down to merit systems being imperfect; that is, that there are biases in judgments of merit, that they are not always implemented as promised, and that they risk creating hubris in the successful and despair among the unsuccessful. Our perspective is that, however valid these criticisms, merit-based systems are still immensely superior to alternatives that have either been tried before or are being proposed now.77 Communist systems, for example, which are vastly more egalitarian, produced misery on an unimaginable scale.

Can newly proposed alternatives deliver better results? Let us consider an example. In The Tyranny of Merit,77 Sandel proposes the following approach: identify some minimum standard that constitutes “qualified” for admission to Harvard or Stanford and use a lottery system to select among those. Specifically, he mentions cutoffs that would treat 50–75% of applicants as “qualified,” which stops short of abandoning merit altogether. He justifies these cutoff points by using anecdotal data about athletes who were overlooked by professional teams in early draft rounds, but who went on to have highly successful careers in their sport. But examples of a few overlooked individuals do not imply that merit-based selection is ineffective—indeed, players drafted early are much more likely to go on to professional careers.79 Sandel also seems to presume that identically capable college applicants will suffer if some end up attending lesser schools. However, in STEM (science, technology, engineering, and mathematics), where education provides objectively assessable technical skills, attendance at a top university provides little advantage in students’ earnings potential. Measured 10 years post-graduation, a top-tier education provided no significant earnings advantage for science majors and at best a marginally significant one for engineering majors.80 Moreover, Sandel seems to be unaware that his strategy, by nature of being based on a lottery, guarantees that many candidates will end up in lesser schools than their equally qualified counterparts, an outcome that a merit system, by its nature, aims to minimize.


6. Exhibits of the Intrusion of Ideology into Science and Attacks on Merit

In recent years, numerous statements issued by scientific societies and papers published in Science, Nature, the New England Journal of Medicine, The Lancet, and other respected journals have been advancing CSJ ideology and attacking science and liberal epistemology. Journals now publish entire topical issues dedicated to CSJ subjects. For example, in 2022, Science published the topical issue “The Missing Physicists: How Physics Excludes Black Researchers”;74,81,82,83 Chemical Education published a virtual DEI collection comprising 67 papers exploring such topics as decolonization of the chemistry curriculum, chemistry and racism, and gender and sexual orientation identities in the chemistry classroom;84 Inorganic Chemistry published an issue celebrating “LGBTQIAPN+ inorganic chemists”;85 World Scientific published the three-volume set Porphyrin Science by Women;86 and Nature published an editorial, “Science Must Overcome Its Racist Legacy,” announcing four forthcoming special issues dedicated to the topic87 (the first issue was published in 202288).

Below, we highlight selected examples of such publications, grouped according to recurring themes. Common among them is revolutionary destructivism, which calls for the established structures and practices of science to be replaced by CSJ-based practices. Words like “excellence,” “impact,” or “quality” rarely appear, or appear only to be problematized (which, according CSJ, can be done to anything4,6). Instead, we see ample mention of “white supremacy,” “discrimination,” “harassment,” “race,” “gender,” “violence,” “intersectionality,” and “marginalization,” typically without citation to supporting evidence, an egregious failure for journals purporting to be about science.

These pieces fail to acknowledge the progress that has been made and continues to be made toward equality, fairness, and justice throughout the Western world.1,2,27,76 Instead, they attribute, generally without evidence, the underrepresentation of any group in any domain to systemic racism or sexism in the present and within the domain itself.76 This precludes an honest appraisal of the root causes of disparities and is likely to lead, therefore, to solutions that are ineffective, unjust, and damaging to science.76

The scientific community must come to the realization that such articles are not innocent expressions of well-meaning individuals. They are not exaggerations or outliers, but are true to the creed of the ideology that produced them.6,14 The sheer volume of these publications illustrates the extent of the ideological intrusion into science.

Below we analyze three recurring themes in these papers: (1) science is white and colonial; (2) science is racist; and (3) merit-based policies should be replaced by identity-based policies. Theme 1: Science is white and colonial

For decades, Critical Theories had been confined to humanities and Studies departments of universities. But the ideas have spread to other disciplines and the outside world, where they have been picked up by activists and the press. Following the canons of CSJ, science is described as “white” and “colonial” and, therefore, should be dismantled. These ideas now routinely appear in some of the most influential scientific journals without citation to actual data supporting their claims. The apex journal Nature has created a “Decolonizing Science Toolkit,”89 which includes articles such as “Institutions Must Acknowledge the Racist Roots in Science,”90 “Decolonization Should Extend to Collaborations, Authorship and Co-Creation of Knowledge,”91 and “Seeding an Anti-Racist Culture at Scotland’s Botanical Gardens.”92

Decolonization is already a reality. For example, in New Zealand, decolonization of the sciences by adding the mythological content from Mātauranga Māori to the science curriculum is now actively pursued throughout schools and universities with the support of the government,33 and any criticism to this is termed racist.101

The decolonization theme has been amplified, ironically, by institutions whose supposed telos is to support science. An article published in Nature attempting to justify the decolonization of science in South Africa states: “Decolonization is a movement to eliminate … the disproportionate legacy of white European thought and culture in education … dismantling the hegemony of European values and making way for the local philosophy and traditions that colonists had cast aside.”38 One might think, the article would identify how, for example, Newtonian physics or Darwin’s biology went wrong and the errors were fixed by indigenous knowledge. It does nothing of the kind. Instead, it discusses the value of greater local involvement in science and having science education address local needs and interests. These laudable goals, which we hope succeed, have nothing to do with “the hegemony of European values.” Indeed, the article acknowledges that “the meaning of decolonization is not well defined …” We doubt it can be because it is ideological rhetoric rather than a scientific statement with truth value.

In 2021, The Lancet Global Health invited and published the opinion piece “Says Who? Northern Ventriloquism, or Epistemic Disobedience in Global Health Scholarship,” which purports to expose “epistemic violence” in the scientific literature.93 The author calls for “epistemic resistance” to disrupt the accepted standards and practices in global health scholarship. She claims, “Epistemic violence is the active oppression by powerful structures to displace the marginalized from socioeconomic and knowledge-creating institutions to suppress their political voices. This exclusion incessantly erases contributions from LMICs [Low and Middle Income Countries] to global knowledge creation.” She cites three sources to justify this alleged “incessant erasure”—all of which include a great deal of historical analysis but nothing recognizable as empirical evidence of said erasure in the present.

Papers calling for “decolonization” of practically every domain of STEMM are mushrooming in the literature, with little opposition. A rare exception37 critiques the notion of decolonizing global health. The authors articulate the harms of the decolonization agenda, namely, that it undermines confidence in scientific knowledge, promotes intergroup and international antagonisms, disregards the possibility of progress, and, most importantly, closes the door to achievable change in an unequal world. Dismantling global health will not give us better treatments for debilitating diseases or tools to control the next pandemic. Theme 2: Science is racist

Race has become a central political and social issue in the U.S. and beyond. Learned societies and institutions, including the National Academy of Sciences (NAS),94 the National Academy of Engineering,95 the National Academy of Medicine,96 and the National Institutes of Health,73 have issued statements asserting, without evidence, the existence of systemic racism among their ranks and pledging to combat it. The American Physical Society, the American Geophysical Union, the Geological Society of America, the Society for the Study of Evolution, the National Association of Geoscience Teachers, and their sister societies outside the U.S. have published similar statements. Numerous university science departments have followed suit. In the journal Science, chemist Holden Thorp claimed (ironically, without evidence) that “evidence of systemic racism in science pervades this nation [the U.S.].”97 In an unsigned editorial, Nature’s editors stated that “scientific institutions were—and remain—complicit in systemic racism” and pledged to “end anti-Black practices in research.”98 The American Chemical Society published an editorial signed by all senior editors alleging the existence of systemic racism in chemistry publishing. Among several action points, they pledged to include “diversity of journal contributors as an explicit measurement of Editor-in-Chief performance.”99

A Nature editorial100 in 2021 reaffirms this narrative: “Racism in science is endemic because the systems that produce and teach scientific knowledge have marginalized and ill-treated people of other skin colors and under-represented groups for centuries”; organizations “must ensure that anti-racism is embedded in their … objectives and that such work wins recognition and promotion”; and “too often, conventional metrics—citations, publication, profits—reward those in positions of power, rather than helping to shift the balance of power.” Nature continued this theme in a recent editorial, calling for the decolonization of science and arguing that past racism has left “an indelible mark on science.” In 2022, the journal released a volume, titled “Racism,”88 which includes personal accounts of several authors of perceived racism throughout STEMM, including artificial intelligence and computer science, genetics, plant biology, and medicine (citing oxygen-sensor inaccuracy in Black people), as well as more general contributions on how to confront “imperialism’s long shadows” and its racist past.

In 2022, Science published the special issue “The Missing Physicists: How Physics Excludes Black Researchers” featuring an editorial “Dismantle Racism in Science”74 and several pieces with titles such as “Can U.S. Physics Overcome Its Record of Exclusion?,”81 “The Toll of White Privilege,”82 and “Fix the System, Not the Students.”83 The recurring themes are that physics is racist and exclusionary, run by a “white priesthood,” and based on “white privilege”; that existing programs do not serve women or minorities, who purportedly need a different educational approach; and that merit-based evaluations must be relaxed to increase diversity in science, and that this will benefit the field.

As is typical when viewed through the lens of Critical Theory, these assertions were not buttressed by actual evidence of systemic racism—the existence of quantitative disparities was the only evidence required.76 This may be valid in a dogmatic ideological framework that attributes all inequality to “isms.” But from a scientific perspective, assertions require evidence and correlation does not imply causation. In fact, the assertion that all inequality in the present is determined by discrimination in the present is readily refuted by evidence. For example, Asian Americans earn more advanced degrees and have higher incomes than do white Americans.125 The notion that all inequality reflects systemic racism leads to the absurd conclusion that the U.S. is an Asian supremacist country. Many more examples of this kind can be found in Discrimination and Disparities.76

Articles accusing science of racism often support their claims by historical examples of scientists who held racist beliefs—like those in Darwin’s day who, while they may have been abolitionists (like Darwin himself), still believed in a racial hierarchy of intelligence with white people on top. But one would be hard-pressed to give examples of institutional features today that foster discrimination and are responsible for the dearth of minority scientists in STEM. For example, the authors of the Nature editorial87 support their claim of current systemic racism by asserting that people like J. D. Watson, C. Murray, and R. Herrnstein are racist. Even if true, three anecdotal cases do not indict science itself as rife with systemic racism. Several contributions to the topical issue on racism published by Nature88 also support claims of current systemic racism by personal anecdotes. A paper in Nature Geoscience titled “Scientists from Historically Excluded Groups Face a Hostile Obstacle Course”103 supports the title thesis by citing a tweet and a peer-reviewed paper based on “an interpretation of the dream of an African American woman” (refs 5 & 6 in 103).

The proposed solutions—to a problem that has not been shown to exist—endanger the integrity of the scientific enterprise. Scientific positions, grants, and article acceptances should be awarded on the basis of their quality rather than treated as commodities to be distributed based on identity categories. The telos of science is the search for provisional truth and the production of knowledge, not the redistribution of rewards to achieve activists’ visions of equity or reparative justice.

Claims of systemic racism in academic research have spilled over into applied domains, notably medicine.25 An article, “An Antiracist Agenda for Medicine,” characterizes the handling of the COVID-19 crisis as “ongoing genocide, shamefully, if quietly, embedded in a centuries-old legacy of structural, scientific and medical racism.”129 That the absurd comparison of the COVID-19 crisis to genocide made it into print is consistent with a growing body of evidence suggesting that, in the “right” circles, one can make almost any ridiculous claim, as long as one frames it as advancing “Social Justice.”130

The American Medical Association has produced a guide to language, asking practitioners to avoid using adjectives such as “vulnerable” and “high-risk” and to avoid saying “target,” “combat,” or other “terms with violent connotation” because they reinforce “narratives that constantly shift and adapt as conditions change and serve to rationalize the privileges of racism that sustain white supremacy.”35 These recommendations and similar DEI guidelines issued by the American Association of Medical Colleges34 are set to be implemented in medical schools’ curricula.

The American Psychological Association makes a lengthy apology to people of color for the association’s supposed role in “promoting, perpetuating, and failing to challenge racism, racial discrimination and human hierarchy in the U.S.”36 They promote a radical, non-evidence-based, untested psychotherapy that encourages patients to see their problems through a lens of power and race, a recommendation flagrantly abandoning known best practices, such as centering therapy on the concerns of the patient, rather than those of the therapist,26 and cognitive behavioral therapy. This is not science; it is ideology and, arguably, malpractice. Theme 3: Merit-based policies should be replaced by identity-based policies

Many scientific fields are now under pressure to rethink how research is conducted. The forms of pressure range from injunctions to increase the diversity of researchers to calls to eliminate merit-based metrics of the performance of students, postdocs, and faculty.74,81,82,83,84,85,104,105,106 The existing standards are purported to be “white,” “colonial,” “sexist,” and insufficiently inclusive. Traditional success and impact metrics (e.g., citations and impact factors) are claimed to be “flawed and biased against already-marginalized groups” and to perpetuate “sexist and racist ‘rewards.’”105

Major scientific journals such as Nature, Science, and their sister publications regularly publish opinions, editorials, and letters to the editor calling for increasing the number of women and selected minorities among tenure-track faculty, graduate students, award recipients, conference speakers, and editorial boards. In response, scientific institutions have begun implementing identity-based practices and social engineering.52,62,107,108 Some faculty hiring committees are prioritizing diversity over merit or even using ideology as a filter by, for example, eliminating candidates solely based on DEI statements.47,48,51

Many scientific societies now encourage or require identity-based quotas for speakers and award recipients.108 NAS now penalizes its nominating committees if their nominations are insufficiently diverse.62,107 If one has any doubt that CSJ ideology is replacing merit-based science, this quote from McNutt (president of the NAS) and Castillo-Page (its Chief Diversity and Inclusion Officer) is the smoking gun: “Not so long ago, the NAS might have naively argued that its membership could not reflect the diversity of the American public it serves until universities fixed the ‘leaky pipeline’ of too many women opting out of careers in scientific research almost before they begin, or until elementary and secondary schools started motivating more students of color to study STEMM disciplines and prepared them for success in college and beyond. But in 2021, it is simply not acceptable to wait for ‘bottom-up’ solutions.”107 This implies that membership in the Academy should reflect an aspirational dream of proportional representation, rather than the real demographics of the most-meritorious scientists. The secretary of the NAS revealed how this will operate: “We assign slots [to different fields] based on the diversity of the lists of nominees that get forwarded” and “If they used [their slots] to pick a bunch of white guys from Harvard, they get penalized.”62

In some ways, this is trivial concerning the production of science. Membership in NAS is not science; it is an honor in recognition of contributions to science. In that sense, it is a reward to be distributed, not a scientific discovery or invention of any import. But if we continue to subjugate meritocracy to CSJ by failing to reward the best-performing individuals and recognize the most creative and influential work, we risk eroding scientific excellence. When NAS signals “this is the way we provide scientific rewards,” other scientific institutions will follow their lead.

Race- and gender-based selection for honors, conference presentations, and awards undermines the achievements of individuals from underrepresented groups by creating an impression that women and minorities cannot compete in an open marketplace of ideas and talent. It is also offensive to know that one’s research was selected, not strictly for its merit, but at least partly due to one’s ethnicity or gender. This is “the soft bigotry of low expectations”—the creation of different standards based on the perceived or real historical oppression of some individuals.75

Some form of affirmative action might be effective in college admissions, when students do not yet possess demonstrated credentials and many have lacked educational opportunities. However, when preferential selection goes overboard, e.g., when the mean scores on admission criteria of affirmative action students is a standard deviation (or more) below those of students admitted under conventional standards, the practice becomes counterproductive in helping underrepresented groups to advance.131 This failure of affirmative action in the U.S. is well documented; despite being in place for more than half a century in U.S. colleges, race-conscious admissions have not led to proportional representation in STEMM.52 The total number of Black students matriculating in U.S. medical schools has not changed in over three decades.131 This is striking because, in the U.S., students from minority backgrounds indicate more interest in STEM than white students: a 1985 study of 27,065 incoming freshmen in 388 colleges found that the initial interest in STEM majors was 53%, 34–35%, and 17% for Asian American, Hispanic/African American, and white students, respectively.52 Despite this initial interest, the rates of graduation with STEM majors vastly differ: 70% of Asian Americans persist in their ambition compared to 61% of whites, 55% of Hispanics, and 34% of African Americans. The disparities are even more extreme at elite institutions.52 The analysis attributes this attrition to academic mismatch—by admitting minority students to schools that do not match their academic preparation, these students are at a disadvantage and often drop out or change to non-STEM majors, ironically, often to identity studies. In better-matched schools, students do well and graduate in STEM fields. Paradoxically, strong affirmative action appears to lead to a decrease of African- and Hispanic-American students entering STEM fields.52

CRT-informed social engineering is now present in every domain of science, including publishing, hiring, and research funding. The Royal Society of Chemistry has issued a quota of 35% representation of women on editorial boards and in reviewer pools108—considerably greater than the current representation of women holding tenure and tenure-track positions in chemistry departments (~20%).132 Australia’s National Health and Medical Research Council will allocate half the funding for its largest research program to women and non-binary applicants.109

Some journal editorials have begun urging authors to preferentially cite “articles led by colleagues from different gender identities and geographical areas,”110 in the spirit of “citation justice.Tools to implement “citation justice” already exist.133,134 The publisher Elsevier encourages authors to apply “citation justice” on a voluntary basis,127 while other publishers have implemented policies, such as mandatory DEI statements,115,128 to that end. The promoters of “citation justice” justify the practice by the assumption that differences in citation rates are due to racist or sexist biases in publishing (135 and ref. 3–16 therein). This, however, is an unsubstantiated claim, as we discuss below.

Claims of bias in STEM, which now pervade the literature, are typically based on anecdotal evidence, superficial analyses, or ideologically based assumptions. A typical example is a paper that alleges the existence of gender bias in chemistry publishing based on a superficial analysis of publication statistics.135 Although the authors found gender differences in various metrics of professional accomplishment, the differences were small—e.g., on the order of one percentage point in manuscript acceptance rates. Moreover, the authors failed to adequately control for potentially confounding factors (e.g., seniority of researchers) that could explain the observed gender discrepancies. Yet, despite this paper’s poor scholarship, it has been cited as evidence of biases in chemistry and used to justify imposing gender quotas on editorial boards and in reviewer pools.108

When confounding factors are controlled, evidence of gender bias in STEM all but vanishes. Controlling for confounding variables, a recently completed quantitative synthesis of the literature on gender gaps in six academic science domains (manuscript acceptance rates, recommendation letters, tenure-track hiring, grant funding, salaries, and teaching ratings) found convincing evidence of bias only in teaching ratings, and the oft-cited gender pay gap of 18%119 was reduced to 4%. In the other five domains, the authors concluded that there has been “no systematic gender bias in the last 10–20 years.”120 Similarly, a recent encyclopedic review of the literature on gender gaps in STEM found that “the evidence for endemic anti-female bias is inconclusive at best,” and that, instead, “the main cause of the gender gaps in STEM appears to be average sex differences in people’s vocational preferences.”

Furthermore, there is no evidence that introducing identity-based biases to the peer review process will do anything to improve science. Adding citational “representation” to redress grievances makes sense only if one views citations as rewards to be distributed rather than as acknowledgments of scientific contributions. Although the current peer-review system is not perfect and is sometimes affected by personal biases, these imperfections do not justify adding non-scientific considerations to review processes. Bias should be eliminated by procedures that cleave to truth and rigorous evidence, not by reversing the direction of the biases or adding irrelevant noise. Intentionally adding biases and imperfections erodes the integrity of the literature.

In a similar vein, institutions justify mandatory DEI training by alleged implicit biases, based mostly on the implicit association test (IAT), which is riddled with conceptual, theoretical, empirical, statistical, and methodological limitations, weaknesses, and artifacts.136 Indeed, there is no evidence that receiving implicit bias training or reducing implicit bias as measured by the IAT reduces discriminatory behavior.137

In hiring at many universities, faculty applicants are now required to write DEI statements.46,47,48,51 In recent faculty searches in the life sciences at UC Berkeley, three-quarters of the candidates were eliminated solely on the basis on their DEI statements.47 Putting aside separate objections that the use of DEI statements to screen applicants constitutes a political litmus test and a form of (possibly illegal) compelled speech, by reducing the viable applicant pool, it likely undermines the quality of science.130 Thus, a brilliant mathematician (or physicist or cognitive scientist) may be filtered out by virtue of having expressed insufficient enthusiasm or familiarity with the particular version of DEI that the institution supports.

DEI statements are often expected to embrace CSJ; statements that express support for the ideals of liberal social justice, such as Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.’s dream of a colorblind society, are rejected. As UC Berkeley’s sample rubric for evaluating diversity statements states, candidates who intend to treat “all students the same regardless of their background” will be given the lowest score.126 In 2021, job advertisements for STEMM faculty often devote more space to DEI requirements than to actual technical qualifications. As McWhorter notes, job advertisements for physicists now sound like advertisements for social workers or anthropologists.138 Some universities have begun to incorporate DEI statements in tenure and promotion.49 The process of evaluation needs to be reformed, according to a 2022 paper in the journal eLife, which provides “A Guide for Writing Anti-Racist Tenure and Promotion Letters.”122 The authors recommend that the letter writers include their positionality statements, invite the evaluation committee to reflect on “white supremacy culture” in academia, and redefine what is considered to be meritorious.

In research funding, some grant programs now require that applications include an explanation of how the proposed project will address the principles of DEI.42,43,44,45,138 Failure to adequately address DEI bears the risk of rejection. Should government funding advance science—fundamental research, energy solutions, health, and medicine—or social engineering? McWhorter notes:

The notion seems to be that practitioners and scholars, across disciplines, must devote a considerable part of their time to putatively antiracist initiatives. It’s a bold proposition, but given how shaky its actual justification is, it is reasonable to think that lately this devotion is being imposed by fiat, as opposed to being an organic outpouring. And if the price for questioning that notion is to be seen as sitting somewhere on a spectrum ranging from retrogressive to racist, it’s a price few are willing to pay. One is, rather, to pretend. 138

Europe, like the U.S., is susceptible to the ideology of identity. One of the five pillars of the 2021–2027 agenda of the European Union is developing a “more social and inclusive” Europe.124 To implement this noble vision, most European calls for STEMM funding (e.g., Horizon Europe) require plans demonstrating how proposed research will benefit underrepresented minorities. Venerable institutions with a history of promoting excellence and being merit-driven, such as the German Science Foundation, the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, and the Max Planck Society, have issued generic pledges to advance diversity, formulated in CSJ terms. More than 200 institutions from around the globe signed the Alba Declaration on Equity and Inclusion, which asserts that bias against women and minorities in STEM is ubiquitous and calls for social engineering.118
7. The Way Forward

Science has been the driving force behind unprecedented improvements in the global quality of life—from advances in medical diagnostics and cancer treatment to the information technology revolution, from the growth of agricultural productivity to the development of sustainable energy. Science and technology are global and highly competitive. If dismantling the merit-based practices of the U.S. and other democratic countries continues unabated, the loss of leadership in developing cutting-edge technologies is likely to eventuate.

For science to succeed, it must strive for the non-ideological pursuit of objective truth. Scientists should feel free to pursue political projects in the public sphere as private citizens, but not to inject their personal politics and biases into the scientific endeavor. Maintaining institutional neutrality is also essential for cultivating public trust in science.65 The rush to create systems institutionalizing racial, ethnic, and gender preferences in college admissions and hiring will further corrode public trust in academia and science (e.g., surveys from the U.S. show that most Americans, including most Americans of color, reject such preferences66). Although no system is guaranteed to eliminate all biases, merit-based systems are the best tool to mitigate it. Moreover, they promote social cohesion because they can be observed to maximize fairness.

Admittedly, meritocracy is imperfect. The best and brightest do not always win. But the idea that meritocracy is nothing but a myth is demonstrably false, indeed absurd. Were it but a myth, college admissions and hiring could be conducted without regard to applicants’ qualifications, and students or employees could be selected at random.

The role of science in rectifying social inequalities goes beyond “trickle-down” effects of scientific progress. Science can help to develop programs addressing both the root causes of inequalities and the effectiveness of remedial policies. Recent works by Banerjee and Duflo illustrate how well-founded scientific methodology can narrow the gap between rich and poor countries.139 Heckman’s work quantifies the impact of pre-school education on students’ success.140 In the field of artificial intelligence, one of the most active areas of research is concerned with discrimination,141 fairness,142 and social accountability.143 The distinctive features of these examples, setting them apart from CSJ, are that they are based on scientific evidence and logic and they address the root causes of inequalities, rather than their symptomatic manifestations.

There is a large literature in the field of psychology on the role that demographic biases play in how we judge individuals.144 Such biases are real and a justified concern, but fighting them with opposite biases and undermining merit is counterproductive. Two of the most robust findings in the literature are: (1) people massively judge others on their merits when their merits are clear and salient; and (2) in such situations, stereotypes and implicit biases145 are minimized. Thus, a sharp focus on merit minimizes bias and maximizes the chances that those who best meet the relevant standards (for admissions, hiring, publication, or anything else) will be rewarded, thereby promoting inclusion. For example, standardized tests can help to fairly evaluate applicants from diverse backgrounds55 and—if used properly—increase diversity.54 A strict focus on merit, properly implemented, also reduces the influence of bias, department politics, nepotism, and favoritism, thus facilitating diversity, while maximizing scientific quality and the public’s confidence and trust in the academy and science.

How do we begin the process of depoliticizing science and strengthening merit-based practices? We offer six concrete suggestions:

  • Insist that government funding for research be distributed solely on the basis of merit.
  • Ensure that academic departments and conferences select speakers based on scientific, rather than ideological, considerations.
  • Ensure that admissions, hiring, and promotion are merit-based and free from ideological tests.
  • Publish and retract scientific papers on the basis of scientific, not ideological, arguments or due to public pressure.
  • Require that universities enforce policies protecting academic freedom and freedom of expression, according to best practices promulgated by non-partisan free speech and academic freedom organizations, such as the Foundation for Individual Rights and Expression.

8. Conclusion

Imbuing science with ideology harms the scientific enterprise and leads to a loss of public trust. If we continue to undermine merit, our universities will become institutions of mediocrity rather than places of creativity and accomplishment, leading to the loss of the competitive edge in technology. Thus, we need to restore our commitment to practices grounded in epistemic humility and the meritocratic, liberal tradition.

We need to be vigilant against the dilution of our merit evaluations by biases, ideology, and nepotism. Moreover, as a community, we should continue to invest in mentoring and education to help people develop their full potential. Adopting the guidelines we have suggested does not mean that we ignore the contributions of past racism and sexism to the inequalities we observe today. It means addressing these issues in a fundamentally positive way—not by introducing diversity metrics into funding or hiring decisions, nor by weakening the standards for university admissions and professional advancement, but by investing in the early pipeline, for example, by strengthening educational outreach and programs to increase access to sustained quality education and early exposure to STEMM.

Scientists must start standing up for the integrity of their fields despite the risk of bullying and verbal attacks; donors and funders should condition their support on non-partisan and rational scientific pursuit. Science as a free pursuit of knowledge untainted by ideological orthodoxies maximally enhances the public good.


9. Afterword

Perhaps the grandest irony of them all, and the saddest commentary on the state of academia, is that this article, defending merit, could only be published in a journal devoted to airing “controversial” ideas.147 As we were finalizing the manuscript for publication, the Office of Science and Technology Policy of the White House released a 14-page long vision statement outlining the priorities for the U.S. STEMM ecosystem.148 The word “merit” appears nowhere in the document. In February, 2023, The National Academy of Sciences released a report titled “Advancing Antiracism, Diversity, Equity, and Inclusion in STEMM Organizations: Beyond Broadening Participation.” The report describes merit as a non-objective, “culturally construed” concept used to hide bias and perpetuate privilege, refers to objectivity and meritocracy in STEMM as myths, and calls for merit-based metrics of evaluation to be dismantled.149


Supplementary Materials

The following are available online at https://journalofcontroversialideas.org/download/article/3/1/236/s1.

References 1

Y.N. Harari, Homo Deus: A Brief History of Tomorrow, New York: Harper (2017). 2

S. Pinker, The Better Angels of Our Nature, Viking Books (2011) and Enlightenment Now: The Case for Reason, Science, Humanism and Progress, New York: Penguin Books (2018). 3

Postmodernism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, link to the article; Critical Theory, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, link to the article; Critical Race Theory, Encyclopedia Britannica, link to the article. See supplemental material for a compilation of quotes from scholarly sources and academic advocates of postmodernism and critical theories. 4

J.F. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, University of Minnesota Press, MN (1984). 5

R. Delgado, J. Stefancic, Critical Race Theory. An Introduction, New York: New York University Press (2001). 6

H. Pluckrose, J.A. Lindsay, Cynical Theories: How Activist Scholarship Made Everything about Race, Gender, and Identity—and Why This Harms Everybody, Durham, NC: Pitchstone Publishing (2020). 7

H. Pluckrose, What Do We Mean by Critical Social Justice, Counterweight (2021), link to the article. 8

Postmodernism and CSJ are broad intellectual enterprises with a literature comprising thousands of books and millions of academic papers and essays. Thus, it is impossible to critique postmodernism or CSJ in toto and, accordingly, we do not attempt to do so in this paper. Indeed, we do not advocate for a wholesale rejection of the postmodern or CSJ perspective. Rather, the purpose of our commentary is to defend and advance the importance of merit in science. 9

We use the term “merit” to mean the rigor, importance, and validity of a scientific idea or proposition or the accomplishments of an individual. 10

J. Rauch, The Constitution of Knowledge, Washington, DC: Brookings (2021). 11

J. Savolainen, P.J. Casey, J. McBrayer, and P. Nayna Schwerdtle, Positionality and Its Problems: Questioning the Value of Reflexivity Statements in Research, Perspectives on Psychological Science (2023, in press), link to the article. 12

R.K. Merton, The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press (1973). 13

H.E. Longino, Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press (2020). 14

A. Sullivan, Removing the Bedrock of Liberalism, The Weekly Dish (2021), link to the article 15

J. Mervis, U.S. Science No Longer Leads the World. Here’s How Top Advisers Say the Nation Should Respond, Science (2022), link to the article. 16

P.R. Josephson Totalitarian Science and Technology, Amherst, NY: Humanity Books (2005). 17

L.R. Graham, Science, Philosophy, and Human Behavior in the Soviet Union, New York: Columbia University Press (1991). 18

S. Zatravkin and E. Vishlenkova, Early Soviet Medicine: Statistical and Narrative Utopias, Kwartalnik Historii Nauki i Techniki 64: 83–106 (2019), link to the article. 19

A.I. Krylov, The Peril of Politicizing Science, J. Phys. Chem. Lett. 12: 5371–76 (2021), link to the article. 20

A. Loeb, Benefits of Diversity, Nat. Phys. 10: 616–17 (2014), link to the article. 21

M. Carey, M. Jackson, A. Antonello, and J. Rushing, Glaciers, Gender, and Science: A Feminist Glaciology Framework for Global Environmental Change Research, Progress in Human Geography, 40: 770–93 (2016), link to the article. 22

As part of Grievance Studies Affair, the following paper was almost accepted (“revise and resubmit status”) into the Women’s Studies International Forum: M. Gonzalez (pseudonym). Stars, Planets, and Gender: A Framework for a Feminist Astronomy. 23

A. Wooldridge, The Aristocracy of Talent: How Meritocracy Made the Modern World, Penguin, UK (2021). 24

D.N. McCloskey, The Great Enrichment: A Humanistic and Social Scientific Account, Social Science History 40: 583–98 (2016), link to the article. 25

K. Herzog, What Happens When Doctors Can’t Tell the Truth? Common Sense (2021), link to the article. 26

S. Satel, Race for the Vaccine, Persuasion (2020), link to the article; When Therapists Become Activists, Persuasion (2021), link to the article; and What is Happening to My Profession? Quillette (2021), link to the article. 27

Digest of Education Statistics, National Center for Education Statistics (NCES), the U.S. Department of Education (2021), link to the article. 28

San Francisco Declaration on Research Assessment, link to the article. 29

L. Maroja, Self-Censorship on Campus is Bad for Science, The Atlantic (2019), link to the article. 30

K. Herzog, Med Schools Are Now Denying Biological Sex, Common Sense (2021), link to the article. 31

S. Ritchie, Science Is Political – and That’s a Bad Thing, Science Fictions (2022), link to the article 32

P. Deift, S. Jitomirskaya, and S. Klainerman, As US Schools Prioritize Diversity Over Merit, China Is Becoming the World’s STEM Leader, Quillette (2021), link to the article. 33

L. Krauss, Indigenous Myth and Science: From Egypt to New Zealand, Critical Mass (2022), link to the article. 34

Association of American Medical Colleges. Diversity, Equity, and Inclusion Competencies Across the Learning Continuum, Washington, DC: AAMC New and Emerging Areas in Medicine Series, (2022), link to the article. 35

The American Medical Association, Advancing Health Equity: Guide to Language, Narratives, and Concepts, (2021), link to the article. 36

American Psychological Association, Apology to People of Color for APA’s Role in Promoting, Perpetuating, and Failing to Challenge Racism, Racial Discrimination, and Human Hierarchy in U.S., Resolution adopted by the APA Council of Representative (2021), link to the article. 37

M. Hellowell and P. Nayna Schwerdtle, Powerful ideas? Decolonisation and the Future of Global Health, BMJ Global Health 7: e006924 (2022), link to the article. 38

L. Nordling, How Decolonization Could Reshape South African Science, Nature 554: 159–62 (2018), link to the article. 39

J. Sun et al., A Systematic Analysis of FDA-approved Anticancer Drugs, BMC Syst. Biol. 11, art. 87 (2017), link to the article. 40

M. K. Parvez and V. Rishi, Herb-Drug Interactions and Hepatotoxicity, Curr. Drug Metab. 20: 275–82 (2019), link to the article. 41

S.M. McFadden, J. Demeke, D. Dada, L. Wilton, M. Wang, D. Vlahov, and L.E. Nelson, Confidence and Hesitancy During the Early Roll-out of COVID-19 Vaccines Among Black, Hispanic, and Undocumented Immigrant Communities: A Review, J. Urban Health 99: 3–14 (2022), link to the article. 42

H. Mac Donald, The NIH’s Diversity Obsession Subverts Science, Wall Street Journal (2021), link to the article. 43

A. Cho, At DOE, Efforts to Address Climate and Diversity Dovetail, Science 372: 1379 (2021), link to the article. 44

“Promoting Inclusive and Equitable Research (PIER) Plans,” Department of Energy Office of Science (2022), link to the article. 45

M. Higgins, Minority Professor Denied Grants Because he Hires on Merit: ‘People are Afraid to Think’, National Post (2021), link to the article. 46

A. Thompson, The University’s New Loyalty Oath, Wall Street Journal (2019), link to the article. 47

J. Coyne, When Commitment to Diversity Outweighs Teaching and Research in a Biology Job (2021), link to the article; Life Science Jobs at Berkeley Give Precedence to Candidates’ Diversity and Inclusion Statements (2019) link to the article; and A Thread about University DEI Statements (2023), Why Evolution Is True, link to the article. 48

J. Poff, UC Santa Cruz Prescreens Faculty Job Applications Based on Mandatory Diversity Statements, Washington Examiner (2021), link to the article. 49

C. Flaherty, The DEI Pathway to Promotion, Inside Higher Ed. (2021), link to the article; and Where DEI Work Is Faculty Work, Inside Higher Ed. (2022), link to the article. 50

M. Wente, At Canadian Universities, Race and Gender Quotas Have Become a Way of Life, Quillette (2022), link to the article. 51

B. Leiter, Diversity Statements Are Still in Legal Peril, The Chronicle of Higher Ed. (2022), link to the article. 52

A Dubious Expediency: How Race Preferences Damage Higher Education, by Gail Heriot (Ed.), Maimon Schwarzchild. 53

J.L. Riley, A Chance to Remove Race From College Admissions, Wall Street Journal (2022), link to the article. 54

Q&A: Stuart Schmill on MIT’s decision to reinstate the SAT/ACT requirement, MIT News (2022), link to the article. 55

N.R. Kuncel and S.A. Hezlett, Standardized Tests Predict Graduate Students’ Success, Science 315: 1080–81 (2007), link to the article. 56

R. Henderson, Don’t End Aptitude Tests, Persuasion (2021), link to the article. 57

L.M. Leslie, Diversity Initiative Effectiveness: A Typological Theory of Unintended Consequences, Academy of Management Review 44: 538 (2019), link to the article. 58

P. Arcidiacono, E.M. Aucejo, and K. Spenner, What Happens After Enrollment? An Analysis of the Time Path of Racial Differences in GPA and Major Choice, IZA J. of Labor Econ. 1, art. 5 (2012), link to the article. 59

A. Chung and L. Hurley, U.S. Supreme Court to Hear Challenge to Race-Conscious College Admissions, Reuters (2022), link to the article; Expert Report of P. S. Arcidiacono, Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. Harvard, No. 14-cv-14176-ADB (D. Mass); and link to the article. 60

S.T. Stevens, L. Jussim, and N. Honeycutt, Scholarship Suppression: Theoretical Perspectives and Emerging Trends, Societies 10: 82 (2020), link to the article. 61

A.I. Krylov, J.S. Tanzman, G. Frenking, and P.M.W. Gill, Scientists Must Resist Cancel Culture, Nachrichten aus der Chemie 70: 12–14 (2022), link to the article. 62

L. Krauss, The New Scientific Method: Identity Politics, Wall Street Journal (2021), link to the article. 63

E. Kaufman, Academic Freedom in Crisis: Punishment, Political Discrimination, and Self-Censorship: CSPI Report No. 2, The Center for the Study of Partisanship and Ideology (2021), link to the article. 64

The degree of capture varies among institutions. Examples of essentially complete capture include the University of San Diego (see The Woke Takeover at the University of San Diego, link to the article) and The Evergreen State University (see How Activists Took Control of a University: The Case Study of Evergreen State, link to the article). 65

D.M. Kahan, Fixing the Communications Failure, Nature 463: 296–97 (2010), link to the article; and What is the “Science of Science Communication”? J. Sci. Comm. 14: 1–10 (2015), link to the article. 66

J.M. Horowitz, Americans See Advantages and Challenges in Country’s Growing Racial and Ethnic Diversity, Pew Research Center (2019), link to the article; N. Graf, Most Americans Say Colleges Should not Consider Race or Ethnicity in Admissions, Pew Research Center (2019), link to the article. 67

J. Coyne, Pinker vs. the AAAS on the Politicization of Climate Change—and Science in General, Why Evolution Is True (2022), link to the article. 68

P. Boghossian, Truth Must be the Highest Priority of a University, in Ben Ik Wel Woke Genoeg? Ed. M. Harlaar, Gompel & Svacina (2022). 69

R. DiAngelo, White Fragility: Why It’s So Hard for White People to Talk About Racism, Boston, MA: Beacon Press (2018). 70

I.X. Kendi, How to Be an Antiracist, New York: One World (2019). 71

R.E. Nisbett and T.D. Wilson, Telling More Than We Can Know: Verbal Reports on Mental Processes, Psych. Rev. 84: 231–59 (1977), link to the article. 72

R. Samra and O. Hankivsky, Adopting an Intersectionality Framework to Address Power and Equity in Medicine, The Lancet 397: 857–59 (2020), link to the article. 73

J. Kaiser, NIH Apologizes for ‘Structural Racism,’ Pledges Change, Science 371 (6533) (2021), link to the article. 74

E.O. McGee, Dismantle Racism in Science, Science 375: 937 (2022), link to the article. 75

J. McWhorter, Woke Racism: How a New Religion Has Betrayed Black America, Penguin Random House (2021). 76

T. Sowell, Discrimination and Disparities, New York: Basic Books (2019). 77

M.J. Sandel, The Tyranny of Merit, New York: Picador (2020). 78

D. Markovitz, The Meritocracy Trap: How America’s Foundational Myth Feeds Inequality, Dismantles the Middle Class, and Devours the Elite, Penguin Press (2019). 79

R.T. Karcher, The Chances of a Drafted Baseball Player Making the Major Leagues: A Quantitative Study, Baseball Research J. (2017), link to the article. 80

E.R. Eide, M.J. Hilmer, and M.H. Showalter, Is it Where You Go or What You Study? The Relative Influence of College Selectivity and College Major on Earnings, Contemp. Econ. Policy 34: 37–46 (2016), link to the article. 81

J. Mervis, Can U.S. Physics Overcome its Record of Exclusion? Science 375: 950 (2022), link to the article. 82

J. Mervis, The Toll of White Privilege, Science 375: 952 (2022), link to the article. 83

J. Mervis, Fix the System, not the Students, Science: 375: 956 (2022), link to the article. 84

Z. S. Wilson-Kennedy et al., Introducing the Journal of Chemical Education’s Special Issue on Diversity, Equity, Inclusion, and Respect in Chemistry Education Research and Practice, Chem. Ed. 99: 1–4 (2022), link to the article. 85

A. Ghosh and W.B. Tolman, Out in Inorganic Chemistry: A Celebration of LGBTQIAPN+ Inorganic Chemists, Inorg. Chem. 61: 5435 (2022), link to the article. 86

Porphyrin Science by Women, ed. F. Dumoulin, T. Nyokong, and P.J. Brothers, World Scientific (2022), link to the article. 87

M. Nobles, C. Womack, A. Wonkham, and E. Wathuti, Science Must Overcome Its Racist Legacy: Nature’s Guest Editors Speak, Nature 606: 225–27 (2022), link to the article. 88

Racism, a special issue of Nature 610 (7932) (2022). 89

Decolonizing Science Toolkit, Nature (2022), link to the article; “This collection of resources provides examples of how institutions and scientific departments are recasting curricula and addressing racism’s influence.” 90

V. Gewin, Institutions Must Acknowledge the Racist Roots in Science, Nature 612: 178–179 (2022), link to the article. 91

V. Gewin, Decolonization Should Extend to Collaborations, Authorship and Co-Creation of Knowledge, Nature 612: 178 (2022), link to the article. 92

L. Nordling, Seeding an Anti-Racist Culture at Scotland’s Botanical Gardens, Nature 611: 835 (2022), link to the article. 93

T. Naidu, Says Who? Northern Ventriloquism, or Epistemic Disobedience in Global Health Scholarship, The Lancet 9: e1332–e1335 (2021), link to the article. 94

Statement by the President of the National Academy of Sciences (2020), link to the article. 95

President’s Statement on NAE’s Commitment to Diversity, Equity, and Inclusion (2020), link to the article. 96

Statement on Racial Equity and the Adverse Effects of Racism by NAM President (2020), link to the article. 97

H. Holden Thorp, Time to Look in the Mirror, Science 368: 1161 (2020), link to the article. 98

Systemic Racism: Science Must Listen, Learn and Change. Nature Commits to Working to end Anti-Black Practices in Research, Nature 582: 147 (2020), link to the article. 99

Confronting Racism in Chemistry Journals, An editorial published simultaneously in several ACS journals (JACS, JCTC, ACS Appl. Mater, etc.) (2020), link to the article. 100

Tackling Systemic Racism Requires the System of Science to Change, Nature 593: 313 (2021), link to the article. 101

T. McAllister, 50 Reasons Why There Are no Māori in Your Science Department, J. Global Indigeneity 6: 1–10 (2022), link to the article. 102

Conference: Gender Equality, Diversity, Inclusion post-Corona: Quo Vadis? Humboldt Foundation (2021), link to the article. 103

A.A. Berhe et al., Scientists from Historically Excluded Groups Face a Hostile Obstacle Course, Nature Geoscience 15: 2–4 (2022), link to the article. 104

L.K.G. Ackerman-Biegasiewicz et al., Organic Chemistry: A Retrosynthetic Approach to a Diverse Field, ACS Cent. Sci. 6: 1845–50 (2020), link to the article. 105

S. Davies et al., Promoting Inclusive Metrics of Success and Impact to Dismantle a Discriminatory Reward System in Science, PLOS Biol. 19: e3001282 (2021), link to the article. 106

L.M. Diele-Viegas, Potential Solutions for Discrimination in STEM, Nat. Hum. Behavior 5: 672–74 (2021), link to the article. 107

M. McNutt, L. Castilllo-Page, Promoting Diversity and Inclusion in STEMM Starts at the Top, Nat. Med. 27: 1864–65 (2021), link to the article. 108

A Framework for Action in Scientific Publishing, Royal Society of Chemistry, link to the article. 109

B. Nogrady, “Game-changing” Gender Quotas Introduced by Australian Research Agency, Nature (2022), link to the article. 110

A.M. Valenzuela-Toro and M. Viglino, How Latin American Researchers Suffer in Science, Nature 598: 374–75 (2021), link to the article. 111

C. Mott and D. Cockayne, Citation Matters: Mobilizing the Politics of Citation Toward a Practice of “Conscientious Engagement”, Gender, Place, and Culture 24: 954–73 (2017), link to the article. 112

P. Zurn, E.G. Teich, S. C. Simon, J. Z. Kim, and D.S. Bassett, Supporting Academic Equity in Physics through Citation Diversity, Comm. Phys. 5: 240 (2022), link to the article. 113

J.D. Dworkin, K. A. Linn, E.G. Teich, P. Zurn, R.T. Shinohara, and D.S. Bassett, The Extent and Drivers of Gender Imbalance in Neuroscience Reference Lists, Nature Neuroscience 23: 918–26 (2020), link to the article. 114

P. Zurn, D.S. Bassett, and N.C. Rust, The Citation Diversity Statement: A Practice of Transparency, A Way of Life, Trends Cogn. Sci. 24: 669–72 (2020), link to the article. 115

S. Else, J.M. Perkel, The Giant Plan to Track Diversity in Research Journals, Nature 602: 566 (2022), link to the article. 116

R. Luna, The MPI Diversity & Inclusion Committee: Sparking Change (2020), link to the article. 117

#ProgressDiversity: More Diversity for Science, Humboldt Kosmos (2021), link to the article. 118

Alba Declaration on Equity and Inclusion, link to the article. 119

H. Shen, Inequality Quantified: Mind the Gender Gap, Nature 495: 22–24 (2013), link to the article. 120

S.J. Ceci, S. Kahn, and W. M. Williams, Stewart-Williams and Halsey Argue Persuasively that Gender Bias is Just One of Many Causes of Women’s Underrepresentation in Science, Eur. J. Personality 35: 40–44 (2021), link to the article. 121

S. Stewart-Williams and L. G. Halsey, Men, Women and STEM: Why the Differences and What Should Be Done? Eur. J. Personality 35: 3–39 (2020), link to the article. 122

The A4BL Anti-racist Tenure Letter Working Group, Equity, Diversity and Inclusion: A Guide for Writing Anti-Racist Tenure and Promotion Letters, eLife (2022), link to the article. 123

Gender Innovations 2: How Inclusive Analysis Contributes to Research and Innovation, Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union (2020), link to the article. 124

European Commission, Priorities for 2021–2027, link to the article. 125

G.G. Guzman, Household Income: 2016. US Department of Commerce, Economics and Statistics Administration, U.S. Census Bureau (2017), link to the article; C. L. Ryan, K. Bauman, Educational Attainment in the United States: 2015. Current Population Reports, U.S. Census Bureau (2016), link to the article. 126

Rubric for Assessing Candidate Contributions to Diversity, Equity, Inclusion, and Belonging, UC Berkeley, link to the article. 127

Working Toward Racial and Social Equity: Research and Commentary, Elsevier (2020), link to the article. 128

D. Sweet, The Inclusion and Diversity Statement – One Year On, Cell Press (2022), link to the article. 129

B. Wispelwey and M. Morse, An Antiracist Agenda for Medicine, Boston Review (2021), link to the article. 130

L. Jussim, N. Honeycutt, P. Paresky, A. Careem, D. Finkelstein, and J. Finkelstein, The Radicalization of the American Academy, in, Zúquete, J.P. (ed). The Palgrave Handbook of Left-Wing Extremism, New York: Palgrave MacMillan (2023, forthcoming). 131

C.T. Laurencin and M. Murray, An American Crisis: the Lack of Black Men in Medicine, J. Racial and Ethn. Health Disparities, 4: 317–21 (2017), link to the article. 132

L. Wang and A. Widener, The Struggle to Keep Women in Academia, CE&N 97 (2019), link to the article. 133

A Gender Citation Balance Indexer Online Tools, link to the article. 134

Citation Transparency Chrome Extension, link to the article. 135

A. E. Day, P. Corbett, and J. Boyle, Is there a Gender Gap in Chemical Sciences Scholarly Communication? Chem. Sci. 11: 2277–301 (2020), link to the article. See references 3–16 citing similar studies carried by Elsevier, Nature Publishing, Institute of Physics, Functional Ecology, and American Geophysical Union. 136

U. Schimmack, Invalid Claims About the Validity of Implicit Association Tests by Prisoners of the Implicit Social-Cognition Paradigm, Perspect. Psychol. Sci. 16: 435–42 (2021), link to the article. 137

E.L. Paluck, R. Porat, C.S. Clark, and D.P. Green, Prejudice Reduction: Progress and Challenges, Ann. Rev. Psych. 72: 533–60 (2021), link to the article. 138

J. McWhorter, Here’s a Fact: We’re Routinely Asked to Use Leftist Fictions, New York Times (2021), link to the article. 139

Press release by the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences; the Sveriges Riksbank Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel 2019 was awarded to Abhijit Banerjee, Esther Duflo, and Michael Kremer “for their experimental approach to alleviating global poverty” 140

J. Heckman, G. Karpakula, Intergenerational and Intragenerational Externalities of the Perry Preschool Project, NBER Working Paper No. 25889, JEL No. C4, 121 (2019). 141

J. Kleinberg, J. Ludwig, S. Millainathan, and C. Sunstein, Algorithms as Discrimination Detectors, PNAS 117: 30096–100 (2020), link to the article. 142

J. Zhang and E. Bareinboim, Fairness in Decision-Making—The Causal Explanation Formula, Proceedings of the 32nd AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence (2018), link to the article. 143

The Fifth Annual ACM FAccT Conference on Fairness, Accountability, and Transparency (ACM FAccT), link to the article. 144

L. Jussim, Social Perception and Social Reality: Why Accuracy Dominates Bias and Self-Fulfilling Prophecy, Oxford: Oxford University Press (2019). 145

R. Rubinstein, L. Jussim, and S. Stevens, Reliance on Individuating Information and Stereotypes in Implicit and Explicit Person Perception, J. Exp. Soc. Psych. 75: 54–70 (2018), link to the article. 146

Kalven Committee: Report on the University’s Role in Political and Social Action, link to the article. 147

We first approached a prominent interdisciplinary science journal with our manuscript, which we thought would be an appropriate venue for our commentary because it had published several perspectives on the topic from the CSJ point of view. We were given approval to submit our manuscript as a perspective but advised to remove the word “merit” from the title by the editorial board, who wrote, “Most readers will immediately associate the term ‘merit’ with the ongoing … debate about merit in college admissions, and the whole concept of meritocracy in education. The problem is that this concept of merit, as the authors surely know, has been widely and legitimately attacked as hollow …. If the authors could use a different term I would encourage that [emphasis ours].” Thus, not only is meritocracy in science a controversial idea, in some circles the very existence of merit as a concept is questioned. So it appeared right from the start that publishing our manuscript was going to be an uphill battle. Indeed, our paper was reviewed and rejected largely on ideological grounds, citing, among other reasons, its “hurtfulness.” We then approached several other scientific journals with informal inquiries about the suitability of the manuscript for publication and the outcome was not encouraging. Therefore, the paper was submitted to the Journal of Controversial Ideas, where we believe it will add balance to viewpoints appearing in academic journals on this important topic.

Ce qu'il vous reste à lire
0 %

Peut-être devriez-vous vous abonner ?

Sinon, ce n’est pas grave ! Vous pouvez fermer cette fenêtre et continuer votre lecture.

    S'enregistrer: